Semantics: The Study of Implication (A Dramatic Reframing)

.........................................................

In this essay, I would like to make a formal submission to the semantics community to retrain its focus on what I believe is the root interest in the field.  I speak here of the field of semantics, not the field of general semantics.  While I talk in this forum usually of general semantics, I pause that discussion in light of some ideas that have surfaced in general semantics to apply them to the field of semantics, and thereby transform the focus of the semantics field.

I submit, in the form of a thesis, the proposition that semantics is the study of implication.  This idea, albeit relatively uninformed by actual professional or academic semantic study, I divine as new, a characterization of which I may be mistaken.  However, I take as lightweight but inspiring support a recent search of the Wikipedia page for “Semantics,” and I don’t find to date the use of the word “implication,” except in a citation pointing not to a study of implication.

Herein, I aim to persuade the reader that semantics deals primarily with implication, and not primarily with definition, signification, or some other more mechanical, mathematical, or otherwise deterministic interpretation of definienda.  By dealing primarily with implication, semantics is properly viewed as a behavioral science, and lexicons like dictionaries are viewed as historical documents telling the general implications of words in their time and times–historical documents of human mental behavior–and not listings of definitions per se.  This is to say that definitions are simply kinds of implications.  To study definitions in the field of semantics is to take merely a special interest inside the overarching field, and insofar as that special interest is rigid, that special interest is a fetishization of definitions.

“The Study of Meaning”

Many sources, whether they be periodical or human, will cite that semantics is “the study of meaning.”  I. A. Richards and C. K. Ogden point out in their famous The Meaning of Meaning that the word “meaning” has a number of different definitions.  Their point demonstrates that the word “meaning” and its counterparts (“mean,” “means,” “meant,” “meaningful,” etc.) have a level of genericity that complicates their absolute and definitivie interpretation in the contexts in which they appear.  That is, the words “meaning,” etc., are generic, and in being generic, they aren’t specific, and in not being specific, they are open to interpretation, and in being open to interpretation, they are plagued with the potential for misinterpretation.  That they are misinterpreted is illustrated by academic and philosophical discussion of meaning throughout civilization, having an undercurrent of the unfamiliar despite being such a familiar, everyday concept.

This is to say that to say semantics is “the study of meaning” is to open up for interpretation what exactly the study of semantics is of.  “Meaning” means what?  What kind of meaning?  Is it the study of words and their definitions?  Is it the study of literary symbols and their interpretations?  Is it the study of terrestrial events and their possible consequences?   Is it the study of the relevance of activities in time toward the achievement of particular goals?  If it is but the study of words and their definitions, why is it not the study of these other events, which are situations in which the word “meaning” is also pragmatically used?

Implication

When we ask the question, “What does that mean?,” in most cases but the truly exceptional, we are asking the question, “What does that imply?”  If we ask that of a word, someone else may follow with a definition, but she may also follow with a synonym, a translation, a photograph, a non-verbal referent like an actual thing, etc.  That is, definitions are not the only answer to that simple question of meaning, and meanings aren’t always definitions.  In fact, a number of referents can meet the criterion we naturally have for calling something “a meaning.”  The word “semantics” and the word “meaning” do not exclusively cover definitions.

Definitions, as well as those other referents, are formally classed as implications.  Lest you think of “implication” as a highfalutin concept, instead it is a simple idea, a cognitive response the human body has to a stimulus.  That is, first there is some sort of stimulus, followed second by neural responses that construct what that stimulus implies to the human.  Meeting in nature a growling wolf with snarling teeth and dripping saliva implies you’re about to be attacked.  Meeting the word “Enter” on a door implies you can pass through and into a store.  There really is no difference between these two stimuli, one non-veral, one verbal, each neurological.  Semantics, I argue, may study both.

But implications manifest in the human body in ways other than because of non-verbal or verbal stimuli.  Reading the news, an editor may posit, “What do the events in Egypt mean for the stability of the Middle East or North  Africa?”  To ask that question is to get one wondering about the implications of the events, to think about consequences.  The events are not language–they are empirical events–but they can still imply things to people, mainly because they can stir implications in people.  For people with no grasp of the happenings in that region of the world, the implications may be few–for example, a 2-year-old experiences few implications in light of the news.  However, a scholar in Egyptian political science may experience countless implications as a result of the news.  If semantics is the study of implication, a subfield of semantics studies the meaning (implications) of world events.

And the answer to the question “What do the events in Egypt mean for the stability of the Middle East or North  Africa?” can lead to many different kinds of answers.  There may be social answers, political answers, geographic answers, geneological answers, cartographical answers, American answers, Libyan answers, Muslim answers, Catholic answers, U.S. Presidential answers, tourismal answers, economic answers, predictive answers, scientific answes, mathematical answers, statistical answers, and the list goes on.  In terms of society, the events imply ___.  In terms of politics, the events imply ___.  In terms of statistics, the events imply ___.  And so on.

Cassius Keyser & Alfred Korzybski

Cassius Keyser, the respected Columbia University mathematics professor whose interest also was in philosophy, covered the topic of implication eloquently in his book Mathematical Philosophy.  While Keyser does not seem to get into covering the human-behavioral component of implication, his friend, engineer and polymath Alfred Korzybski, regarded thinking as behavior, and thus would likely regard implication as behavior as well.

While not explicitly saying so, Korzybski preferred the term “semantic reaction,” which might be interpreted as “implication” given how he uses the term as referring to the reactions humans have to words and events in connection to their meanings.  Korzybski spoke of total-body (“organismal”) reactions to words and events–which is to discuss, I argue, the psychosomatic implications of words and events like “Enter” and a snarling wolf.  That is, in my opinion, when Korzybski was talking about semantic reactions, he was talking about implications.  The name of the field he developed, “General Semantics,” I argue in an earlier essay simply means “General Implications,” and his field is not so much about words but about non-aristotelian thinking, and the general implications of non-aristotelian thinking.  (His major work, Science and Sanity, is subtitled An Introduction to Non-Aristotelian Systems and General Semantics.)

Applying These Insights to the Field of Semantics

Any derivative field of semantics that tries to lock up absolutely the meaning (implication) of a word is on the wrong path, at least on the whole.  Given that human behavior is variable, what is implied by words varies with each individual.  Of course we know this on the whole, but semanticists (or their respective philosophers) may still not believe so.  For example, the Wikipedia entry for “Semantics” contains the phrase “the meaning of signs,” as if single meanings could be applied to signs.  A more scientific formulation would be the phrase “the meanings of signs,” which implies that signs have meanings, not some single meaning to be understood.  That is, signs imply multiple ideas, no question, so signs have multiple implications, never just one implication.

Semantics may focus itself on different kinds of implication in its division into subfields.  For the historian interested in the implications of words over time, especially as phrased into other words (definitions), that semanticist might be involved in “verbal lexical semantics.”  That is, verbal lexical semantics is the study of the implications of words as manifest as other words.  If the semanticist is more interested in the implications of words not as words but as pictures or some other more visual referent, that semanticist might be involved in “non-verbal lexical semantics.”  Non-verbal lexical semantics is the study of the implications of words as manifest as empirical entities.  To use a more korzybskian phraseology, for the semanticist interested in non-verbal lexical semantics, that semanticist studies extensional semantics, while the semanticist interested in verbal lexical semantics studies intensional semantics.

But what of the semanticist who studies the consequences of world events?  That editor who poses the question “What is the meaning of these events?” may be implying “What consequences may occur because of these events?”  That semanticist is a non-linguistic semanticist.  That is, that editor “reads” events as if they were language, and makes characterizations about what those events imply.  Many fields offer their own non-linguistic semantic account of events.  A forensic scientist (“criminal semanticist”) might say, “If the defendant’s DNA was on the victim in that manner, that means the defendant had contact with the victim.”  A meteorologist (“weather semanticist”) might offer for the viewer the implications of a cold front’s approaching the area.  A statistician (“statistical semanticist”) might offer his insights on which player to bat in light of what that slugger’s stats imply in the moment.  Excuse the exaggeration, but non-linguistic semanticists are “everywhere.”  They ask the question about meanings (implications) about given ___s.

Now, Please Inform Me

With these claims, I realize they may be misinformed or juvenile.  However, I hope they are anything but.  I hope they get you thinking about the field of semantics, and open it up away from some kind of quest for 1:1 correpondence between word and definition.  Semantics deals with implication, not just definition, and with that broad reframing I believe is the potential to open the field up for more valuable contributions to society.  As we better understand language, we better use language.  At least I think that’s what I’m implying.

Please comment below.  Again, semantics is the study of implication.

COMMENTS

Leave a Comment (0 So Far)


See also: , , , , , , , , , , , ,


Indexes, Labels, Undefined Terms, Oh My!

.........................................................

Alfred Korzybski puts a lot of importance on the use of extensional devices to aid in a person’s becoming more extensional. By that he means becoming more oriented to and aware of the silent level, also known as the non-verbal level. One particular device he promotes is indexing. Indexing is the use of, say, subscript numbers to distinguish terms individuals. For example, this list includes indexes (rarely called “indices” in general semantics) on terms that denote individuals: Smith1, Smith2, Smith3, etc.

Reading an unpublished lecture by Korzybski, I came to see that the use of indexing is especially important when you’re deailng with labels. By “labels,” I mean simply words or phrases that stand for a particular thing. The phrase “Ben Hauck” is a label that stands for me. The word “zebra” does the same, only for the black and white striped mammal. Indexes help to distinguish one-individual-called-“zebra” from another-individual-called-“zebra.” Chain-indexes are another extensional device, and they are strings of subscripts. For example, Smith11. Chain-indexes are meant to distinguish, say, different states of the thing-labeled. If you had a wooden chair in a dry attic and then that “same” chair in a humid kitchen, you might label the first chair11 and the second chair12, wherein the second subscript represents the different states of the chair, but the first subscript denotes that it’s the “same” chair in each instance.

Now Korzybski doesn’t say it too often in his currently published work–at least from what I could see–but from what I measure, he meant “labels” and “undefined terms” to mean basically the same thing. In fact, a label is a kind of undefined term … but you have to come at labels from a particular perspective to understand this characterization. Korzybski often talks about undefined terms when having students research dictionary definitions of words, then the dictionary definitions of the words in the definitions. Eventually, he claims, students start to define words by other words circularly (say “length” by “space” and “space” by “length”). These words he called “undefined terms.”

But in another breath, these words are actually defined–they are extensionally defined, representing particular ideas, concepts, formulations, objects, individuals, etc. These undefined terms are merely labels. Korzybski says as much in his to-be-published “Difficulties in Learning to Apply General Semantics” (ETC: A Review of General Semantics 2011).

Indexes help to distinguish labels so you don’t think this is that. Imagine how valuable labels are in distinguishing identical twin babies in the nursery! If they’re both marked by their last name “Smith,” the index helps to distinguish between which Smith to avoid confusion of the twins. No index? Then presumably the twins are interchangeable, as Smith and Smith are (labeled as) one and the same.

COMMENTS

Leave a Comment (0 So Far)


See also: , , , , , , , , , , , , ,


Meaning, Definition, Implication

.........................................................

We assume that when people use words, those words have some kind of meaning.  When we don’t know the meaning of a word, we consult the dictionary.  The dictionary provides a definition for the word.  That definition is supposed to help guide understanding about what that word meant when that person said it.

Truth be told, it is not dictionaries that write what other people say.  Instead, people use words, and they happen to use them in historically measureable ways, at least on the whole.  “Enough people” use a word in a particular way, then it may meet the criteria for entry into a dictionary with a definition that generally matches historical use to that publication date.

But a dictionary does not account for what this particular word means in this particular situation.  In fact, a word can assume a meaning independent of the dictionary’s meaning.  While this notion may be a no-brainer to you, from my experience, people who would regard themselves as quite intelligent don’t think a word can mean something other than what’s in the dictionary.  Use a word in a way deviant from dictionary meaning, and said person would reject your meaning before allowing it, on the grounds that the definition is not in the dictionary.

Meaning and definition could be thought of as implications.  That is, a word implies particular ideas, and those implications are called “meanings” and they’re also called “definitions.”  If we think of words as having implications, we realize a little bit better that context can affect the implications of a word.  Say the word “nigger” in a linguistics class, there’s a set of implications; say “nigger” on the street in the South and there’s another set of implications.  What’s implied by the word in one context is not necessarily implied in the next context.  This understanding helps to defeat any preconceptions that words have definite, unwavering meanings.  Instead, they have variable implications.

Thinking sonically, a word is but a sound.  It is recognized by humans as a symbol.  As a symbol, it is assumed to imply something.  That is, it’s assumed that the sound is intended to bring something to mind.  I say “grasshopper” outloud; you hear what sounds like the word “grasshopper”; you look on your shoulder in case you see one perched there.  If you see a spider instead, you are perhaps more surprised than when you see a grasshopper.  A spider wasn’t implied by the sound “grasshopper.”

Thinking graphically, a word is but a blot.  It also is recognized by humans as a symbol.  And just like a sonic word, the graphic word is assumed to imply something.  Something comes to mind when a human reads a word.  I write “grasshopper” and you think grasshopper, or maybe you think of more words like “cricketlike thing.”  You probably do the latter if you have never seen a grasshopper.

That is, a word can have an extensional implication or an intensional implication.  Extensional implications are actual things, behaviors, people, places, etc., that words imply.  Intensional implications are just other words that words imply.  If I write “Austin,” an extension is your pointing it out on a map, while an intension would be the phrase “the capital of Texas.”  Note that an intension is just a special case of extension: Intension is when the actual thing you’re pointing to is other words.

What’s interesting to note in addition to the above is that implications vary from person to person.  I might say “indigo,” and that word may imply a set of specific ideas to a fashion designer, yet other things to a fashionably illiterate person.  (I joke that men just don’t have concepts of colors like “fuchsia,” “indigo,” and whatnot.  We just call them “pink,” “purple,” etc.)  Implications are not absolute; they are variable, varying from person to person.

Furthermore, implications may be contrary to standard definitions (implications) of terms.  A teenager may say, “I don’t have any friends,” not realizing she’s saying this to a decent friend.  But while the decent friend might point this contradiction out, the decent friend might have been implied in the teenager’s statement as an exception.  Granted, these are the stupid verbalizations that general semantics tries to dismantle; general semantics tries to get people to talk more accurately about empircal reality.  But I’m saying that some face-value statements may have implications that are contrary to their standard meanings.  Flash back to the 1980s and see what answer you get to Michael Jackson’s question “Who’s bad?” and see if you get a list of criminals, or a list of cool people who might otherwise be considered quite “good.”

This post explains the power of the notion of implication.  Definitions and meanings are but two types of implications.  What others are implied from this post?

COMMENTS

Leave a Comment (0 So Far)


See also: , , , , ,


Korzybskiism

.........................................................

Alfred Korzybski introduced his notion of non-aristotelian thinking over three editions of his book Science and Sanity: An Introduction to Non-Aristotelian Systems and General Semantics.

One stumbling block for people learning about his ideas (contained within the subject called “general semantics”) is the term “non-aristotelian.”  Readers probably don’t know what “aristotelian” means.  If they think they do, they might wonder what aspect of Aristotle’s life is negated with the term “non-aristotelian.”  Was Korzybski negating Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics?  Or his Poetics?  Or something else?  Just reading the word “non-aristotelian” offers no clues.

In truth, Korzybski uses the term in a rather particular way.  Fortunately, though, he provides a lot of examples of what is represented by the term “non-aristotelian,” and what is represented by its counterpart term, “aristotelian.”  Consult the Second Edition of his book for a list of what constitutes each kind of thinking, but for some rough synonyms, think “modern scientific” for “non-aristotelian” and “pre-modern scientific (or even pseudo- and unscientific)” for “aristotelian.”

But with these relatively easy synonyms at hand, I find that the word “non-aristotelian” requires maybe a bit more clarification.  If general semantics is considered but one non-aristotelian system, how do we distinguish it from others?

I propose this term: “korzybskian.”  It’s not an unfamiliar term, but it might be unfamiliar within this particular context.  What I propose is that we use the word “korzybskian” to denote the specific kind of non-aristotelian thinking Korzybski talks about in Science and Sanity and in general semantics as a whole.  That is, Korzybski’s non-aristotelian thinking is korzybskian thinking.  And as a result, “korzybskian” inherits the meaning “modern scientific.”

So non-aristotelianism would be korzybskiism.  And the modern scientific thinking that Korzybski promotes would be korzybskian thinking that he promotes.

This suggests that S. I. Hayakawa’s thinking within general semantics (which Korzybski inevitably took issue with) might be termed “hayakawan thinking.”  Or maybe it could be called “korzybskian thinking to an extent.”  Any of us within general semantics probably exhibit korzybskian thinking to varying extents.  We’re non-aristotelians, but we’re specifically korzybskian non-aristotelians.

Should another non-aristotelian formulator come along to take issue with aristotelian thinking, and develop something distinct from korzybskian thinking, then there would be that new formulator’s ism.  Is there as much room for another, as Korzybski suggests?  It’s hard for me to tell.

From aristotelianism to korzybskiism.

Quite an honor, Count.

COMMENTS

Leave a Comment (0 So Far)


See also: , , , , , , ,


Search this Site


[]


 

Tags

alfred-korzybski aristotelianism cassius-keyser concept conflict definition engineering extension extensional-orientation game-theory gantt-chart general-principle-of-uncertainty generic-terms goals human-engineering identity implication improv insane insanity intension is-of-identity language language-as-generic manhood-of-humanity marketing mathematical-philosophy meaning non-aristotelianism non-elementalism personal-engineering productivity sane sanity science science-and-sanity semantic-reaction semantics structural-differential thinking time-binding unsanity values walter-polakov ways-of-thinking